Can Private Vice Produce Public Virtue?

Detail of Ambrogio Lorenzetti's Allegory of Good Government (1338-1340), discussed below.Detail of Ambrogio Lorenzetti's Allegory of Good Government (1338-1340), discussed below.Wikimedia

Since at least the eighteenth century, this question has often been debated in economic terms. Some philosophers, notably Bernard Mandeville, claimed that vices such as avarice, pride, and vanity are necessary for a well-functioning economy — and a well-functioning economy, they argued, is critical to the public good. Many contemporary American readers probably hold a position like this to some extent. Today, we might be reluctant to call consumer desire and the pursuit of wealth, convenience, and luxury “vices,” but we doubtless recognize these as forces driving the modern economy, producing technological advances, lower unemployment, and higher standards of living. In this sense, at least, we might be inclined to concede that private “vice” produces public virtue. But, in fact, the old argument is far from resolved.

For centuries, many thinkers in the West agreed with certain classical Greek and Roman authors who saw a link between private (or personal) virtue and the public good, between the health of the soul and that of the city. In Book II of Plato’s Republic, for example, Socrates draws an analogy between man’s justice and the justice of the polis. The analogy goes both ways: possession of the virtue of justice in the individual helps to produce its possession in the political community, while political justice contributes to justice within individuals. More broadly, the whole character of the polis — its governance, its values, its culture — affects the character of its members, just as the character of the members affects the character of the polis.

Socrates concedes that in each polis there are inevitably men of all types of vices and virtues. Tyrannies, for instance, are not composed entirely of tyrants. Nevertheless, he insists, the citizens of a tyranny will, on the whole, be marked by the character of slavery as their wills develop in response to the stifling and overbearing will of the tyrant. As Socrates explains to his interlocutor:

“Recall the general likeness between the city and the man, and then observe in turn what happens to each of them.” “What things?” he said. “In the first place,” said I, “will you call the state governed by a tyrant free or enslaved, speaking of it as a state?” “Utterly enslaved,” he said. “And yet you see in it masters and freemen.” “I see,” he said, “a small portion of such, but the entirety, so to speak, and the best part of it, is shamefully and wretchedly enslaved.”

Many of the great thinkers of the Christian theological and philosophical traditions, including both Augustine of Hippo and Thomas Aquinas, agreed in the main with this account of how private virtue is connected to the public good. They accepted as obvious that private vice (or virtue) leads to public vice (or virtue) — and the other way around. For societies to be healthy and well-ordered, families must produce good citizens; for families to produce good citizens, statesmen must embody the virtues they wished to see prevail in their societies and to enact and enforce laws that incline people to cultivate virtue. Character — both in those who governed and those who were governed — was as important as the form of government itself.

The political theorist David Miller begins his wonderful Political Philosophy: A Very Short Introduction (2003) by musing on the fourteenth-century fresco series by Ambrogio Lorenzetti called The Allegory of Good and Bad Government. Emerging from the classical tradition, Lorenzetti takes for granted that the moral characters of both rulers and subjects are deeply connected. The fresco depicts the virtuous ruler in the middle of a flourishing city, surrounded by figures representing the virtues of courage, justice, magnanimity, peace, prudence, and temperance. By contrast, the vicious ruler, who rules a city marked by instability and disorder, is placed among figures who represent vices including avarice, cruelty, and pride. Fear dominates the vicious city: “a city under military occupation, and a barren countryside devastated by ghostly armies,” as Miller writes.

Within a few centuries, the assumptions informing Lorenzetti’s frescoes would be shaken by a new set of arguments about vice and virtue. Where Lorenzetti praised temperance and prudence, later thinkers would make cases against them. “Luxury,” Bernard Mandeville wrote in 1705, “employ’d a million of the Poor, and odious Pride a Million more.”

Mandeville’s long poem The Grumbling Hive: or, Knaves Turn’d Honest defended vice against the moralism of English political ideology famously expressed by Jonathan Swift, among others. Mandeville is explicit:

Envy itself, and Vanity,

Were Ministers of Industry;

Their darling Folly, Fickleness,

In Diet, Furniture and Dress,

That strange ridic’lous Vice, was made

The very Wheel that turn’d the Trade.

The very vices that Lorenzetti portrayed as being opposed to civic well-being — vanity, pride, avarice — are here portrayed as essential to public well-being.

For Mandeville, a society flourishes because of and not despite private vice. “Thus every Part was full of Vice, yet the whole Mass a Paradise.” Even though at the personal level vices of self-seeking abound, that very viciousness conduces to a good society. “Such were the Blessings of that State; their Crimes conspir’d to make them Great.”

But this is merely one half of Mandeville’s account. If an abundance of certain vices can lead to paradise, an abundance of certain virtues leads to despair and poverty. He writes that amid the plenty that vice provides, the hive is “bawling” about the proliferation of vice. These hypocrites, benefitting from their bounty, pray to Jove for virtue, and angry Jove complies, giving them the virtues for which they plead. The hive soon realizes its error:

But, Oh ye Gods! What Consternation,

How vast and sudden was th’Alteration!

In half an Hour, the Nation round,

Meat fell a Penny in the Pound.

….

All Arts and Crafts neglected lie;

Content, the Bane of Industry,

Makes ’em admire their homely Store,

And neither seek nor covet more.

Unable to protect itself and unmotivated towards industry, art, or craft, the hive relocates to the hollow of a tree to live “blest with Content and Honesty.” Mandeville’s rejoinder to the classical view does not simply dismiss virtue nor favor vice but playfully reconfigures their relationship.

Lorenzetti’s and Mandeville’s allegories couldn’t be more opposed. Each takes for granted the same catalogue of virtues and vices, and each assumes that there is a connection between private morality and the public good; yet, each draws an opposed conclusion. For Lorenzetti, pride and vanity must give way to virtues such as selflessness, moderation, and justice, without which social harmony is impossible. For Mandeville, on the other hand, a society lacking vanity and pride will be poor, not rich, and will produce its own and different vices, especially sloth and lack of industriousness. Later Enlightenment philosophers, including Adam Smith and David Hume, would echo and elaborate on Mandeville’s ideas.

Many of us today will likely be sympathetic to Mandeville’s view. In general, we applaud industry, reward ingenuity, and praise technology, production, and the pursuit of wealth. The “contentment” that motivated the hive to retreat into the hollow of the tree is no virtue of our age. We often concede, implicitly or explicitly, that self-interest underlies industriousness and material success; and if so, self-interest must not be bad. Such a culture is not always hospitable to virtues such as charity, understood as complete regard for others, and those associated with religious belief, such as devotion, obedience, and contemplation — all of which tend to subtract from the self-interested pursuit of success.

But there are reasons to suspect a future return to older conceptions of virtue and the related notion, depicted by Lorenzetti, that virtuous character is necessary for a healthy society.

First, recent economic developments may suggest the unsustainability of ever-increasing patterns of consumption. This is only partly a claim about environmental degradation. It is also a claim that harkens back to the insight of the classical tradition that the desire for worldly consumption can never be satisfied — that happiness is not a consequence of the pursuit of material things. Mandeville and his heirs are right to note the relative wealth and comfort of societies propelled toward industry by self-interest — if not by avarice and vanity. But what would they make of the less desirable characteristics of some of those societies? Are unhappiness, boredom, and despair vicious consequences of private vice — or of virtues in the making?

Second, even advocates of the Mandevillian approach praise the older virtues, whether implicitly or explicitly. This we might call the “eternal return of virtue.”

Indeed, Mandeville’s argument about the social benefits of private vice depends upon the classical understanding of vice and virtue to an important extent. His allegory presumes a certain kind of citizenry, one that possesses some of the classical virtues. For example, the citizens who by their avarice devote themselves to production in order to meet their own or their neighbor’s desires cannot help but find themselves in a communal context on which they depend for their own well-being. Thus their productive activity requires not only self-interest but also interest in the good of the community. They are not, in other words, simply vicious but display an admixture of vices and virtues. Adam Smith, in discussing sympathy in his Theory of Moral Sentiments, admits that:

How selfish soever man may be supposed, there are evidently some principles in his nature, which interest him in the fortune of others, and render their happiness necessary to him, though he derives nothing from it except the pleasure of seeing it.

Or we could even say that these vices, such as avarice and pride, if they are to be understood as in fact good, still depend on the classical understanding of virtue as a kind of moderation exercised in community: Rulers and lawmakers would encourage people to behave in these now “virtuous” ways, while genuinely vicious people — pursuing their self-interest to the point of cruelty toward others — would break these laws and harm the public good. So Mandeville’s inversion of virtue and vice still rests on the classical view.

Thus the classical and modern traditions both agree that most people are a combination of virtue and vice. In praising virtue or counseling societies to seek virtuous leadership or laws aimed at the flourishing of virtuous citizens, we must acknowledge, as did Mandeville and his heirs, that people are not always as they should and can be.

Discussion Questions:

  1. Does the kind of argument Mandeville makes require a population not merely familiar with but also possessing a certain amount of virtue?
  2. If the account presented above is true, what are the possibilities and limitations of the law? Can we expect the law to guide people toward the acquisition of virtue, or ought the law merely carve out spaces for people to pursue happiness as they see fit and punish when those spaces are transgressed?
  3. Should we hope and work for virtuous leadership, or trust that whatever the characters of the leaders we get, all will work out in the end?

Discussion Summary

In responding to the question “Can private vice produce public virtue?” I tried to breathe life into the classical view that answered, in the main, “No, it cannot.” The classical philosophical and theological traditions instead saw strong corollaries, if not actual causation, between the character of a people, its governors, and the well-being of society. For them, a society of rotten or vicious people could not produce “public virtue,” whether that means good governance or thriving economic well-being.

We saw, however, the strength of a contrary view that I typified by reference to Bernard Mandeville. Mandeville rejected (quite consciously) the classical view and argued that viciousness in the form of selfish interest would produce thriving societies. Without viciousness (envy and vanity, for instance) not only would society be poorer economically, the arts, crafts, and even diet would wither. Good society requires bad people.

The difficulty — or strength — of Mandeville’s view lies, I believe, in its proximity to the truth about us: we do seem productive when motivated by a competitive spirit. When we’re driven by urgent needs, or sense that we might lose our jobs, or that someone is getting ahead of us, we seem to step up our games, work harder, produce better. But the classical theorists understood that there was both good competitiveness and bad. Good competitiveness arose not from self-interest, but from a regard for others; its satisfaction came in setting goals for the easing of other’s pain or discomfort, or the generation of their awe and wonder. Great craft-making, medicine, and art arose out of this impulse to create, restore, and beautify, not from a desire these philosophers and theologians understood as insatiable: the desire to dominate others. (St. Augustine was among those who referred to the “libido dominandi” at root in human sin. No achievement or victory could quench that desire.)

Furthermore, I argued, the Mandevillian view is predatory on the classical view of virtue, both because of its reliance upon classical terms and categories and — much more damningly — because of the abundance of the virtues that remain in Mandeville’s citizenry, which supposedly benefits from vice. Truly vicious people care not for the hive (the community); they care only for themselves, whether they’re in power or powerless. No society could be formed with such people; all societies require a minimum level of justice — the willingness to render to each his or her own — even the hive.

Respondents to my argument raised a number of great questions: about Mandeville’s intent, liberty and community, vicious leadership, the problem of “dirty hands,” and more. They’re the type of questions all teachers love: respectful, pointed, and informed. One thing that was brought out — and is worth identifying for future discussion — concerns the relationship between freedom and community. At its root, this disagreement over virtue and vice traces back to one’s views about human liberty and man’s place in community. Some — perhaps those who believe that “vice produces virtue” — see community as a concession to human imperfection, something we wouldn’t have if we were perfect. Thus, the requirements of community become infringements on human liberty, given over grudgingly and, perhaps, even provisionally. I’m often drawn to that view; freedom is such a great good, one that few would relinquish. But freedom is also an achievement. One need only look to Europe, the continent that incubated many of the political freedoms we enjoy. Financial, political, and civil instability stain the continent today. Freedoms Europeans have articulated over centuries and enjoyed just as long are eroding as instabilities increase — and how could they do otherwise?

In the end, freedom requires community. Freedom requires cooperation — cooperation not based in self-regard, but other-regard. Because freedom is such a great good, one should strive to share it with sibling, spouse, neighbor, and even stranger.

New Big Questions:

  1. Is freedom comprehensible without community?
  1. Is a completely vicious society conceivable?
  1. Could Mandeville’s account be adapted so as to accommodate a classical notion of virtue?

13 Responses

  1. Samantha Piercy says:

    Dear Mr. Capizzi,

    Was de Mandeville being polemical when he claimed that “vice” is the basis of the public good? I mean, did he really think the pursuit of wealth, etc. was vicious — but led to good things — or was he arguing instead that economics teaches us that these behaviors are really virtuous precisely because they lead to good, whereas apparently virtuous behavior often lead to bad results? Thank you.

    • Joseph E. Capizzi Joseph E. Capizzi says:

      Dear Ms. Piercy:

      Yes, he was being polemical; he was challenging a dominant view and doing so in the manner of the age, with rhetoric and whimsy. That said, he was also serious about reconfiguring what some regarded as a vice (self-interest) as, in fact, a good, as you said, because it leads to good results.  

      We have to be wary, however, of “good results” justifying things that we may have other good reasons to understand as bad. One of our interlocutors asks a similar question, so I’ll get to that in response to him.

      Thank you.

  2. Look, government has a monopoly not only on legitimized force but on legitimized evil. It is evil to steal; but not evil to confiscate for taxes. It is evil to murder; but not to protect from attack or assault. But as Machiavelli stated, a prince can’t use evil all the time but only when there are emergencies such as when a nation is being founded, to abolish corruption, and to banish obstreperous elements and mass migration invasions when necessary. Virtue, as defined by Machiavelli, was not being pious, or moral or pure but having the courage to lose one’s soul for the nation when situations demanded it (Machiavelli never wrote the ends justify the means – that is a bad translation of what he wrote). Yes, any nation or city cannot run based on the principles of the Sermon on the Mount, but civic religion may be important not only to individuals but to nations. So we should pick leaders on how we think they are going to use evil — for good or for bad, full well cognizant that there is no way of knowing ahead of time if an action is going to end up creating good or bad in many cases. Was Truman evil in using an A-bomb on Japan? Was Churchill evil in allowing the German bombing of the English City of Coventry instead of evacuating the city because to do so would have alerted the Germans that the British had broken the German military codes? Was Reagan’s plausible denial of Iran-Contra guns for drugs evil? What about Bill Clinton bombing a pharmaceutical factory in a wag the dog operation to divert attention from his sex scandals? Or Hillary Clinton and the Obama administration using a phony story about a video inciting the attack on our embassy in Benghazi? Or did Obama’s avoidance of using force in the Mideast resulting in massive waves of immigrants which could threaten internal political stability and create more war a good thing? Are the Clinton’s actions morally equivalent to what Truman, Churchill and Reagan did? Or does Donald Trump’s buying and operating casinos pale by comparison? We don’t know because we aren’t having a national discussion on how each candidate would use evil — for good or bad. And the above abstract discussion doesn’t further such a discussion either.

    • Joseph E. Capizzi Joseph E. Capizzi says:

      Dear Mr. Lusvardi:

      There’s a lot in your question, and I’m going to ignore most of it and get to what I think is at its heart: your opening claim that government has a monopoly on legitimized evil. I think that’s flat wrong. Governments (and other sources of authority) exist to serve some good. In the service of that good they have rights and privileges to do things that others —normally — may not. They may not contravene the moral law (the “natural” law), but they may act in ways available only to them.

      Think of the family: in a family, a true community by almost any consideration, parents have obligations and privileges that children do not. Parents are due “respect” different from that children show one other. Parents can punish. Siblings typically cannot punish one other, unless delegated that authority by parents. 

      The same is true of governing authority: it has a monopoly, as you put it, over the power of judgment and punishment in a community whose good it serves. It does so on behalf of that community, and its acts are judged by its service of that good (and that community). It goes without saying that governments often do bad things.

      As you point out or seem to concede, many evil things are done by governments in the name of suspected outcomes, and the supposition seems to be that those outcomes justify those evil things. The political philosopher Michael Walzer has written a great deal on this. He calls it the “problem of dirty hands,” and no doubt he and you are right that those in authority often dirty their hands with evil acts. I’d love to take this issue up in a longer essay — maybe a future “big question?” — for now let me just say that I disagree with you and him.

      Finally, sorry you don’t like abstract discussion! Abstract discussion, I believe, is good for the soul — and for the community!

      Thank you!

  3. jbsay says:

    Mandeville has not made an argument, he has observed a fact.

    Modern developments have not challenged that, on the contrary they have reinforced it.
    “unsustainability” arguments are Malthusian nonsense – that even Malthus ultimately rejected.

    Steve Jobs has done more to improve the world than Mother Theresa. That offends our values, but it is still true.

    The root of the philosophical problem is that Freedom is the foundation of morality.
    Where we reduce liberty – beyond that to use force or fraud to infringe on the liberty of others, we harm ourselves and our future.

    • Joseph E. Capizzi Joseph E. Capizzi says:

      We’ll have to agree to disagree on Steve Jobs and Mother Theresa!

      I think if you look around the world you’ll see that liberty is an achievement of well-ordered societies. Where there is no government (e.g., Libya, or Afghanistan), there is no liberty. 

      The ancient Greeks and Romans often used analogies to athletics when discussing this: to be a great athlete requires great discipline and coaching. To be a great (and free!) team requires the same. Because, for instance, of his subjection to coaching and discipline, Steph Curry is free to be excellent at basketball in a way that I’m not.  

      Thank you!

  4. Isaac Albert says:

    Does the classical view you describe make any sense in a pluralistic context, where different citizens (or communities of citizens) may have different, sometimes conflicting, conceptions of “virtue”?

    • Joseph E. Capizzi Joseph E. Capizzi says:

      Dear Mr. Albert:

      Yes! Certainly, that there are multiple conceptions of virtue makes agreement more difficult. But there are a few points to make note of.

      First, the ancient Greeks and Romans were themselves writing in “plural” societies where multiple beliefs and views found voice. We think we’re unique in that regard, but I don’t think that’s right.

      Second, I think there are certain claims people of quite different beliefs nonetheless share. For instance — and I think this is important for the end of my argument — most if not all people want and do what they understand to be good for them (or those around them). They — you, I, and these people — identify certain things as good (basketball, abstract thought, cigars, family, and on and on) and order our lives around their pursuit. We sacrifice some things (sleeping in late, say) for these (e.g., getting in shape). There will be wild disagreement about which of these is actually good (sleep! No, abs!). But even within or beneath that disagreement, there is the basis of conversation and even argument. And that’s a good thing, I think.

      Thank you.

  5. Pamela Ronson says:

    Thank you for writing this.

    From a Christian perspective, it sounds like the world you describe does not take into consideration the Fall.

    Arguably, couldn’t it be the case that something like Mandeville’s view is the best we can hope for in a fallen state, when people are vicious by nature?

    • Joseph E. Capizzi Joseph E. Capizzi says:

      Great question, Pamela, and, of course, the tradition is sensitive to the effects of sin on humans in society. You’re right if you’re suggesting that despite the “virtues” of good governance, sin will still occur and no society will be absent its influence. We are only ever talking about “relative” virtue in society, and you’re correct to worry about that.

      I think where Mandeville’s account goes wrong is in assuming that the corrosive effects of sin will be undone by the productive activity of vicious “hive” members. That is what I meant by my second point regarding the “inescapability” of virtue. Mandeville’s account, in my view, is parasitic on virtue. All the productivity of the hive he champions really is explicable not in terms of vice but of virtue, even in imperfect men and women. Because most shopkeepers are not actually motivated by selfishness (vice) but by some real good (e.g., the desire to bake good pizza, or interest in taking apart and fixing cars, or love of teaching — all virtues), they commit to those practices and try to do them well. Were they actually vicious more often than virtuous, we would not see the cooperation, the creativity, or the commitment necessary for productive society (or the spaces created that vicious people take advantage of). We would have disorder; that beehive would suffer colony collapse!

  6. Allan Meissner says:

    Could a vicious leader produce a virtuous society? Is such a thing possible (and how would it affect your argument)?

    • Joseph E. Capizzi Joseph E. Capizzi says:

      Yes, Allan, but despite himself. The vicious leader, the tyrant — in older philosophy and theology — was the leader who served his own good, who took himself to be the measure of all communal activity. As the true measure of communal activity is the good of the community (the “common good”), this has a perverting consequence. I think it’s within the realm of possibility that such leadership nevertheless produces a relatively virtuous society, but it wouldn’t be attributable to the leader’s virtues so much as to those of his community and their capacity to overcome his poor leadership.

  7. webandnet says:

    Thank you Professor Capezzi,

    I don’t have any answers, but kind of believe in Platonic-Socrates models. As I recall, Socrates in Republic only barely mentions what specific traits are virtues and vices, and most of the Republic is about how the process of building a just state, and more often, a just individual. And as the just state requires the emergence of a Platonic guardian king, I think it’s fair to say the Republic is more so about the process of a just individual.

    Republic goes through this in 10 books of reasoned discourses, with the final result being– be just and good things will result.

    Again, notice there’s very little said in Republic as to exactly what the character traits of being just are. In fact, the Platonic model is to simply do one’s role in life. So, if this means being a businessman in a free market economy, this means being a free marketer, with lying, greed-motivation, … all thrown in.

    But if one steps outside of one’s role, injustice begins to occur, as according to Socrates.

    When the economic infrastructure of an economy changes, as I read Plato, he is less concerned about how wealth is distributed and more concerned about who has power control. And the Platonic guardian kings and warriors aren’t exactly wealthy.

    When your discussion discusses “virtues” and “vices” from Socrates to Middle Ages to contemporary meanings, the characteristics of these change vastly. But, a maxim to promote for all the virtue of doing public versus private good is questionable. But it is important for those with power.

Leave a Reply to Joseph E. Capizzi Cancel reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *